Intentionality, in flesh and blood
Toward a fore-contact psychopathology
Intencionalidade, em carne e osso
Fronte ao ciclo do contato psicopatológico
Jean-Marie ROBINE
Institut Français de Gestalt-Therapie, França
Published in
International Gestalt Journal
Vol. XXVI, nº2, Autumn 2003
Publicado no
Gestalt International Journal
Vol. XXVI, nº2, Autumn 2003
Resumo
Trabalhando na perspectiva de campo requer uma mudança radical na aproximação do encontro terapêutico. Nós precisamos focar no que é chamado “a situação” e o conceito de intencionalidade deve ter uma grande importância. A função-personalidade do mesmo sempre leva a intenções repetitivas por atos que previnem contatos com a novidade. Por essa razão, gestalt-terapêutas podem frutiferamente “voltar “ ao conceito de intencionalidade, com prioridade para qualquer formação de intenção consciente ou agencia. Meu ponto de vista é que a intencionalidade de um que está na presença de outra pessoa tem que ser conquistada através da afetividade, que é, por via na qual o outro é afetado pelo encontro. Longe de qualquer diferenciação prematura ou assignação de responsabilidade sem estar atento pré ou não consciente intencionalidade deve ser uma aproximação conforme vai se tornando cada vez mais atenta, e disponível para novas provisões diferenciadas. Como resultado dessa mudança proposta, uma nova base é dada para a psicopatologia do contato. Os terapeutas se auto-descobrem recebendo novos significados.
Palavra-chave: Gestalt Terapia; Intencionalidade; Ciclo do contato; Situação; experiência; intuição; encontro; vago; confuso; não consciente; inconsciente; corpo.
Keywords: Gestalt-therapy; intentionality; fore-contact; situation; experience; intuition; encounter; vague; confused; non-conscious; unconscious; body.
This Arabic
legend is related by Medard Boss to facilitate our comprehension of the role
of the analyst, and to cut short what he called, “All the chatter about
the ‘transference’.” Without the introduction of another person,
the situation is a dead end; without the generosity of that other, without his
gift—a thing indispensable that must rapidly become “dispensable”—the
impasse remains. Such is the presence of the psychotherapist. Such is the unfolding
of the therapeutic encounter.
The clinical and psychopathological analysis of the experience of another person,
insofar as it is possible, can only be effected within the encounter.
On Heidegger’s own account, it was precisely this that Ludwig Binswanger,
Boss’s longtime comrade, overlooked in his attempt to elaborate a psychotherapy
under the sign of phenomenology. In his Zollikon Seminars, for over a decade,
Heidegger received at his home, several times per year, an audience of medical
or psychiatric students. In these seminars, Heidegger decried Binswanger’s
“total lack of comprehension of his thought,” an incomprehension
tied to the fact that Heidegger’s Daseinsanalytik had nothing
to do with solipsism or subjectivism, but rather with a ‘being, with other
beings’. “For me, it is a question of you, and for you, of me,”
he was accustomed to say. Psychotherapy can only be approached as discipline
for two (à deux personnes), and it should be theorized as such. An impossible
wager? A thousand year long tradition of speaking of the other as though he
existed outside the gaze we cast upon him, which is a gaze formed by the co-created
situation, has led us to approach the other as though he could be revealed to
‘me’ outside of me, outside my intentional aim [visée], and
outside our encounter itself.
Goodman proposed a Gestalt therapy that stands opposed to that tradition. At
the heart of his work written with Perls, the paradigm of the organism/environment
field postulates the priority of indifferentiation in the experience of the
I and the You: “Experience is prior to the ‘organism’ and
the ‘environment’, which are abstractions from experience.”
It is from experience that the work, which takes place in the therapeutic encounter,
should begin (it owes itself that departure), and it is from there that I would
like to start, to develop this essay.
1. Psychotherapy Approached as a Situation
A number of thinkers in the social sciences today agree that we should consider
the personality as arising so strictly from the situation in which it is engaged,
that it can never wholly depart from it and can thus only ever react to its
situation from within its situation. In a prior study, I underscored
the importance that the founders of Gestalt therapy attributed to the concept
of situation, to the point of seeming to prefer the reference to “the
situation” over the concept of the “field” in their reflections.
Psychotherapy is firstly the construction of a situation, and we can readily
apply to the latter the definition of situation given by G. Debord: “The
concrete construction of momentary life environments and their transformation
into a higher passional quality [en une qualité passionnelle supérieure].”
What we call the social situation is a structure of possibilities that I create
with the other, and which in turn creates us respectively. Clearly, the therapeutic
situation defines my presence and my intention as a psychotherapist, just as
it defines the presence and expression of my client. The situation hardly invites
the latter to give me his “pot roast recipe,” but he may come to
do so nonetheless. If the tradition impels us to think of this event as resistance
or as some other critical mode of contact, another gaze could just as readily
call our attention to our patient’s project, to his intention, as well
as to our own solicitation.
Nevertheless, although the patient’s “I am”—which gets
declined according to the personality mode of the self—is one of the results
of his experience, it is no less (and fundamentally) a play of representations
and rhetorical attitudes. If narrative identity, as it is called today, can
designate one of the possible declensions of the self, it cannot embrace them
in their totality. Gestalt therapy comes to temporalize and delocalize the approach
to this concept of the self, thanks to the radical turn that it imposes on the
self. Narrative identity, contrariwise, is readily envisioned as static; it
frequently lets itself be apprehended as a structure, or a character, thanks
to its fixity, which is at least sufficient to give us the impression of permanence
and continuity in time. Rightly or wrongly, I recognize the same ‘I’
in him who I was a few decades earlier. This is, moreover, why G. Yontef defined
a structure as “a process that evolves very slowly.” This need for
stability and continuity forecloses access to the novelty of situations and
opens us to the repetition of experiences, including the most painful ones.
The subject approaches situations in which he finds himself in light of his
narrative identity; and in the patient-therapist face-to-face, the psychotherapist
is likewise readily credited with another narrative identity, generally implicit,
tied to the presuppositions and needs of the subject. These presuppositions
have more ‘reality’ to them than does observation, since perceptions
or sensations in the situation are rarely called forth as reliable material.
“I would like to touch on such and such question,” says the patient,
“but I am afraid…”
“Could you identify how it is that I am causing you to feel fear?”
“Oh, you’re not doing anything…It is I! I am always afraid
of speaking of these things…”
This condensed version of an interaction, while typical in its banality, is
born out of representations the patient has of himself and which bring him a
certain comfort. It contains the a priori denial that the other could intervene
in any way at the level of the experience that is lived in the moment of the
situation. A certain form of 1960s and ‘70s psychotherapy—and of
Gestalt therapy in particular—advocated this “taking responsibility”
for what can be thought, sensed, felt, enacted, or lived. It seems to me to
go against the perspective of the field, in that it constitutes what I would
call a “premature differentiation,” because it rests upon an equally
premature individuation.
If the process of differentiation and individuation concerns the psychogenesis
of each one of us, and if it is progressively and for the most part elaborated
in the first moments of life, it nonetheless seems to me that each situation,
each encounter, each experience reopens the metaphoric construction site, in
so far as the subject opens to differences, novelty, uncertainty, or to the
unknown.
2. Intentionality
Developed by Edmund Husserl, who made it the central concept of his philosophy,
the term intentionality was introduced into psychology before Husserl by Franz
Brentano in the second half of the 19th century. The perspective that guided
Brentano consisted in separating psychology from the natural sciences. To that
end, he sought to elaborate a psychology that refused to make the psyche into
an object liable to be apprehended by the methods of the natural sciences and
which, on the contrary, would rest on “experience.” Brentano was
thus one of the first to speak of the exteriority of psychic life, seeking to
construct a “psychology without the soul” that would be a psychology
of perception and experience. It is not unreasonable, then, that Gestalt psychology
and phenomenology would each consider Brentano as their precursor. Some hundred
thirty years later, it is anything but certain that Brentano’s enterprise
succeeded, given the still current, pseudo-scientific propensity to consider
the soul of the other person as some reified object for examination.
“What characterizes every psychic phenomenon,” wrote Brentano, “is
what the mediæval Scholastics called intentional presence, and what we
could ourselves call…a relation to some content, a direction toward an
object…or immanent objectivity.” Later on, Husserl will refine the
concept of intentionality (when he specified that consciousness is not a container,
but is rather the signifying intention) by defining it as the tension of consciousness
toward that which it signifies: “To have meaning, or to intend some meaning,
is the fundamental character of all consciousness,” as he summed it up
in his famous formula. The present moment contains an inherent future [avenir
inherent], an orientation, and a direction. We can compare this to Goodman’s
correction to the famous “here and now”: “and Next.”
Here, now, and next.
If the developments of the concept of intentionality concerned above all mental-consciousness,
and particularly the world of representations, certain authors nevertheless
enlarged the field of possibilities. For example, Maurice Merleau-Ponty, in
his Phenomenology of Perception, maintains that all signification and
every speech act are rooted in bodily intentionality. Levinas, then Searle,
emphasized in turn the domain of sensations. Today, it is clinical psychology’s
turn (in J. Chemouni’s voice ) to lay claim to intentionality as the object
of its own definition.
The choice of this concept implies the ground principle according to which the
human being could not be reduced to its physical nature (“the organism”);
that it is, instead, always in relation to an “object,” whether
real or imaginary. The human being is always directed toward something;
for instance, toward an object that has neither existence nor ‘objective’
meaning in itself, but acquires these thanks to the intentionality that aims
at it. In fact, and clinical practice brings this clearly to light, the existence
of an object, represented or representable, is not the essential condition of
intentionality. One may sometimes speak of an “intentional state or content
without an intentional object.” Often enough, a more or less elaborate
labor of unpacking is necessary, in order that an object might find its intentional
state.
3. Intentionality in Situation
Every situation, more specifically every interpersonal situation, mobilizes
intentionality in each of its protagonists. The force mobilizing this intentionality
can be designated and theorized in different ways. Freud spoke of it in terms
of the drives and, following Groddeck, elaborated his theory of the Id, the
first reservoir in the psychic economy. (It is, moreover, important to remember
throughout what follows in our reflection, that when Freud attempted to theorize
the psychic instances [Id, Ego, Superego] from a dynamic and psychogenic point
of view, he set up the ego and the superego as progressive differentiations
of the id.) In his time Goodman introduced the concept of the “id of the
situation,” a way of localizing the origin of the drive motion in the
situation itself, in preference to any localization in the organism or in the
psyche itself. The human being gives form to the situation as the situation
gives form to the human being. “Situations are that to which subjects
adjust via the definitions they give to them.” This movement
of contact and reciprocal constitution founds the human being as actor and beneficiary,
as acting and acted-upon in one and the same process.
If the Id takes shape in a situation, then it is in the situation too that intentionality
becomes an intention. It is there that the ‘Id’ comes to be felt,
to be affect, word, contact, act, behavior, or interaction… If Groddeck
could argue, “man is lived by the Id,” it is no less true that,
starting from the ‘id of the situation’, or from the ‘drive
id’ (if we want to preserve the intra-psychic model), modulation and formation
[modulation et mise en forme] are the act of the self, whose constitutive
dimension is the Id.
In lived experience, the subject readily localizes what is felt, what are behaviors,
etc. as its own belongings [comme des appartenances propres]. The subject
explains or justifies them in the personality mode (the “narrative identity”),
and situates himself preferentially in an ‘I’, which he claims is
free and conscious. This blocks off the regulatory force [contrôle]
that the situation exerts over his experience. Could we not claim, instead,
that one of the functions of psychotherapy consists in dismantling this often-implicit
representation, to reconstruct an individuation better articulated through the
consideration of successive contacts and situations? Could we not postulate
that, in the field of experience, intentionality constitutes what is proper
to the subject—constitutes and defines him—and that we place his
intentionality as a response to the situation or as an initiative, since intentionality
shall give birth to forms?
4. How to Know the Intentionality of the Other Person?
The
saying of the felt experience [le dire de l’éprouvé]
In Gestalt therapy’s non-dualistic perspective, that is, in taking up
a position beyond what Perls and Goodman called “false dichotomies”
like that opposing the body and the mind, nothing can be thought outside the
bodily experience [ressenti corporel]. It would thus be incoherent
to dissociate, or oppose a thought- or deliberated-intentionality to a corporeal
intentionality, even if this lay outside the field of consciousness. Our approach
readily gives privilege of place to the patient’s statement of what is
present to his immediate consciousness. Beyond this limit, psychotherapy proposes
a veritable training in the expansion of the field of consciousness into the
domains of sensation, emotions and sentiments, gestures and behaviors, thoughts
and memories, representations and fantasies, perceptions of the environment…
In the first phase of the construction of the Gestalt, it is a matter of allowing
the emergence or development of a clear figure that could thereupon be deployed.
This amounts to the “drawing together” [ratissage] of partial
experiences in immediate consciousness with those that come up, assemble, conflict
with, or dialectize the experience in a specific direction of meaning. Every
clinician knows how readily the illumination of the coincidence between a patient’s
anecdote, a bodily experience associated with it, and the gestures that accompany
it, etc., structures an orientation noticeably different from the orientation
engaged on the basis of spoken words alone (i.e., words intentionality verbalized,
thereby having become themselves an intention)-- words which may have been spoken
with no regard for the situation itself.
If intentionality is ‘directed toward-‘, then its meaning should
be sought in the situation as a whole, that is, in the field understood as a
“structure of possibilities,” where these possibilities cannot be
reduced to the single ‘organism’, or even the single psyche, as
too many clinicians would seek to limit it.
Intuition
Clinicians
frequently evoke intuition to designate the modality that opened access, for
them, to the other and thus permitted, after all, them to construct some intervention,
sometimes highly relevant. Although some would remind us that this mode of access
to the other is not free from attributions of meaning and projection, or even
from counter-transferential stakes [enjeux contre-transférentiels],
intuition nonetheless permits a knowledge or awareness [une connaissance],
often unrepresentable and inexpressible, of certain components of the patient’s
experience.
My hypothesis is that this intuition is formed at the crossroads of perception
and resonance. The therapist’s self-knowledge, which he owes to his personal
therapy and his supervision, allows the practitioner to elucidate certain components
of resonance that may be in play in the process. It remains for us to come back
to what has been perceived, sometimes without consciousness, treated with extreme
rapidity and turned into a synthesis that may appear passive. What, then, are
the linguistic and bodily signals; what are the vocal and sub-vocal, the contextual
and atmospheric signals perceived by the clinician and immediately synthesized
into a global and implicit signification?
It is necessary, moreover, not to lose sight of the fact that intuitions, like
perceptions, are organized equally by the knowledge, the science and experience
of the clinician. It would be difficult for me to have the intuition that this
person before me was frozen with shame-- against which he was struggling, that
he may have been maltreated or the victim of abuse, or that his depression was
the consequence of a crypt or a ghost—if the theories implied were totally
foreign to my own reflective markers [repères de pensée].
The Encounter with another Intentionality
The essential
postulate of Gestalt therapy rests upon contact. The human being is fundamentally
contact, creative or conservative adjustment within an environment. It is in
and through alterity that intentionality exists. The therapeutic encounter is
an encounter of intentionalities, each calling to the other and in this way
refining it. Through the encounter, intentionalities take the form of intentions.
In a prior study, I invoked the concept of affordance to enlarge the
spectrum of linguistic possibilities that should permit us to speak in terms
of a field and not just according to the solipsistic conception. This neologism
was forged by Gibson, father of eco-psychology, from the verb to afford,
which can be paraphrased as “to have the means to do something.”
It thus designates a characteristic that refers at once to the ‘organism’
and to the ‘environment’, to the fundamental properties that determine
the way in which ‘the object’ can be used. A chair offers support;
its affordance lets me envision sitting down, in connection with my intentions,
perceptions, and possibilities.
Affordance is at work in the therapy session, as it is in every situation. The
patient perceives the psychotherapist and his affordance; this will mobilize
those “uses” that the patient will be able to make of him, while
extinguishing others. My perception of a chair can entail the wish to sit down;
if I need to accede to an object out of reach, high up in my library, I shall
perceive a certain number of affordances in the situation: a chair, a chest
on which to climb. I could even organize inhabitual affordances; perceiving
in telephone books a means to raise myself up, or even the possibility of using
someone in the room as short ladder. Contact with my environment reveals me
to myself and actualizes certain of my potentialities, at the same time as I
bestow on my environment potentialities perhaps unexplored up until then. But
these attributions nonetheless take account of the possible affordance of the
object: I will not perceive in the pocket calculator on my desk the possibility
of accessing a shelf beyond my reach. “Situations do not provoke our actions,
but neither do they represent the simple background against which we realize
our intentions. We do not perceive a situation in function of our aptitudes
or our present dispositions to act,” Joas wrote. In the therapeutic encounter,
we are each for the other, consciously and unconsciously, the essential, constitutive
element of the situation.
The Other Person Affects Me
It is a matter
of common sense and experience to recognize that the other person affects me
from the moment I am in his presence. He affects me, that is, he brings me to
feel [me donne à ressentir], to imagine, to think, to infer,
and to experience bodily and emotionally… Even my neutrality—if
such neutrality exists—or my indifference, is not the pure product of
my will or my choices. My lived experience [éprouvé]
is a tie. It is tied to my intentionality, to be sure, but also to the presence
of the other and his own focus or intending.
My working hypothesis consists in claiming that consciousness of my lived experience
in the here and now of the situation is a privileged instrument of knowledge
of the intentionality of the other. I would be tempted to juxtapose this assertion
to Perls and Goodman’s remarks about emotion, when they say: “Emotion
is the immediate consciousness that integrates the organism-environment relationship.
As such, it is a function of the field. […] In the sequence of figure
and ground formations, emotions take control of the motivating force of desires
and appetites […] (Emotions) are means of cognition. […] They represent
unique information on the state of the organism-environment field.”
What I feel in the presence of the other is thus an indicator of what is in
the field. It speaks of me, speaks of the other; it speaks of the situation,
of the atmosphere, and it speaks of our encounter. I agree completely with Perls
and Goodman when they acknowledge that, as cognition, emotions are fallible,
but one can correct them—indeed, cultivate and refine them. And above
all, one can speak or state them as indicators of what is.
When a woman I am following in group therapy begins speaking a confused language
on the verge of incoherence, when her incoherence is accompanied by diverse
vegetative manifestations, onomatopoeia and stammering (bafouillages),
the more I seek to understand her the less I understand. The sole information
to which I can hold fast at that particular moment is what I feel [mon éprouvé],
which gradually takes the form of a desire to take her in my arms as I might
do with a child, and at the same time the desire to strike her! Now, when I
name these for her, she calms down and begins to speak of the abuse she experienced
as a child—an abuse she had never brought up before—in which she
already experienced violence and tenderness woven together. It was in that direction
of meaning that her intentionality, or that of the situation, thrust her confusedly.
Conscious and Non-conscious Intentionality
In the working
perspective of Gestalt therapy, it does not seem to me to make sense to rely
on some differentiation between what it could mean to raise something--as other
approaches do—from consciousness or the unconscious up to the level of
intentionality; this is a dissociation that Perls and Goodman ranked among the
‘false dichotomies’. Our approach, centered on the process of consciousness
or the becoming-conscious [devenir conscient], does not require the
postulate of a “site” from which intentions might arise that were
possibly contradictory to those already present in consciousness. In this sense,
the symptom constitutes something unavoidable in regard to the question of intentional
aiming, which must bring together what is conscious and what non-conscious in
the experience, in order to be unfolded in view of its becoming explicit. The
child who at a given moment fails in school is certainly not conscious that
he aims to arouse the attention and supportive presence of his mother, in order
to forestall with this the intensification of the mother’s depression.
Nevertheless, as long as some intentionality is not brought to light—which
does not necessarily imply bringing it to consciousness—and other modalities
of reaching the same, essential objective are not elaborated, the symptom will
resist, in search as it is of acknowledgement.
This is why it seems fundamental to me, when we undertake the work of unfolding
or analyzing a symptom, clarify its impact upon the patient’s repertoire,
how it may be experienced, how it affects the other person, and how it motivates
actions in response. These shall figure as givens, essential to venture meaning
hypotheses about the intentionality of the symptom.
When Gestalt
therapy states that the symptom begins by being—at the moment of its constitution—a
creative adjustment to the situation or an attempt, however awkward, to resolve
the problem encountered, it acknowledges implicitly the intentionality of that
symptom. The symptom is a trying- or a meaning-to-say addressed to someone [vouloir-dire
adressé].
Synthesis
Basing my remarks
on the works of Brentano, Husserl, and some of their successors (without pledging
complete allegiance, nonetheless, to their arguments), I have sought to show
how the concept of intentionality could prove valuable in the domain of psychotherapy.
Other Gestalt therapist authors, notably Pietro Cavaleri, have placed this concept
at the center of their thought. Yet it seems to me impossible to follow Cavaleri
in his definition of intentionality, since he assimilates Goodman’s “deliberateness”
to Husserl’s intentionality. That way, intentionality becomes, for Cavaleri,
a characteristic of the self in the mode of ego functioning. This conception
of intentionality probably corresponds to a contemporary use of the term, as
when one gives excuses, for example: “I did not do this intentionally.”
There, intentionally clearly corresponds to “deliberately.” For
my part, I would situate intentionality as constitutive of the emergence of
the figure, and I would thus see it as tied more to the “id of the situation”
and to its “…and next,” in a field perspective. If individuation
is to be sought, as I have proposed, on the side of bringing to light the reflections
of this intentionality, then I can only approach it in the clinical situation
in vagueness and confusion [dans le vague et le confus]. Only by starting
from deliberate intentions and working back to that imprecise intentionality,
which speaks as readily of self as of the other and of the situation, can we
disengage [désenclaver] from the self a part of the play of
representations established in advance by the personality function, in order
to allow it (the self) to accede to an ego mode solidly tied to the id of the
situation. It is therefore to a psychopathology of pre-contact that our reflection
will bring us; it is that which will constitute the second section of our essay.
II
The Vague and the Confused
It is to Eugene Minkowski that I owe the above mentioned two concepts--the vague
and the confused. They seem to me particularly appropriate for evoking this
phase of the process of construction and destruction of gestalts, which is situated
at the moment of emergence and/or the construction of the figure; that is, at
the fertile exit from the void that, according to Perls, defines the zero point,
the before and the after, of every gestalt.
In the therapeutic process, such as the gestalt therapist expresses it, each
sequence is ordered as a “dance” of figures and grounds. Over the
course of the pre-contact, a figure is constituted and gradually differentiated
from the ground. The background of the figure—or simply its ground—nourishes
and sustains the figure, and it is only in the relationship between the figure
and ground that we encounter meaning. The figure gives meaning to the ground,
which, without it, would only be confusion and vague associations, just as the
ground gives meaning to the figure that it raises and sustains. This figure-ground
relationship is intentionality, meaning direction, and excitation-toward. In
the following phase of setting in contact [mise en contact], the intentionality
of the figure-ground relationship will gain fullness and precision, clarity
and firmness, through the unfolding of contact according to predominantly active
and deliberate modes.
Sometimes the patient comes to a session with a firmly constituted theme, problem,
demand, or emotion. This formation, this meaning constitution was effectuated
in advance and the figure that he thus brings with him is, in a sense, the bud
ready to burst open.
Yet this figure is already filled with history and representations, language
and presuppositions. “The meaning bank is the individual’s memory.”
It is not that I would claim to be able to arrive at a tabula rasa, free of
the impact of the personality-function in the formation of the experience to-come
[l’expérience à-venir]. There is nonetheless a
certain play we must introduce into what might otherwise be a set of gears,
too well oiled. We introduce a measure of uncertainty, even doubt. This is what
the Gestalt therapist does (sometimes intuitively), when he refuses to take,
as is, the figure (or screen-figure?) that the patient brings to him, but rather
unfolds it with him. In so doing, the therapist returns in a sense to the conditions
of its elaboration. He returns to the bringing to light of the very materials
used in the figure’s construction. He combs through [ratisse]
and rejoins the elements constituting the ground: thoughts, experiences, sensations,
gestures, analogical language, associations, verbal and nonverbal expressions,
sentiments and emotions, fragments of signification, etc. Aiming to reach the
background of the figure provided, this work often redistributes the excitation
and—precisely because it takes the situational present and the presence
of another person into account—inflects and recomposes the direction of
meaning; it complexifies intentionality by amplifying the confusion. Minkowski
clearly showed how what should remain united or whole sometimes finds itself
separated; he called this phenomenon, “disjunction.” To its contrary—which
Minkowski called the “tie” that binds, albeit abusively at times—he
opposed what should remain separated. If he showed clearly how these phenomena
are at work in certain pathologies characterized as epilepsy and schizophrenia,
Minkowski also specified how, according to more indistinct modes, they operate
in the world of forms. These figures we find brought to us are filled
with ties and disjunctions, tied to history, to narrative identity, to context
and to many other factors—and it is in this precise place that “play”
and mobility should be introduced. To be sure, new disjunctions and ties will
not fail to arise, which will perhaps become the objects of new upheavals. It
is in the activation of these processes that a fundamental part of the therapeutic
work operates (the foundations). And it is there that the term “work”
takes on its full meaning—a term with which I am quite content when I
think that one says of a fine wooden instrument that the wood “works.”
“We now have reality before us anew, in its primary fullness. Now, in
accordance with various demands, we cut slices or sections out of this reality.
It is in this way…that we come to pose the “object” before
us. We do this not by separating it from other objects…but by cutting
out all that gravitates round it, all that envelopes it primitively and attaches
it to the whole. That is, we cut out all that living and moving atmosphere into
which it is plunged (that atmosphere in which everything seems to have to be
confounded), by finding there simultaneously its original source--made up of
that breath of poetry that passes through reality and belongs to it by the same
right that prose does, made up likewise of that sphere in which words forming
images and metaphors experienced (and accessible to each of us) find their place
and translate, at almost every instant and in so expressive a way, that side
of life.” Would it not suffice, in Minkowski’s magnificent description,
to speak of the “figure” instead the object, to rediscover, at work,
that process of construction on which the patient and the therapist collaborate?
But this disjunction dialectizes with the tie that binds: “Life is in
no way made up of objects situated in space, nor of facts situated in time.
Life is made of that dynamism that governs everything. In man, we also find
the need to follow this path; to attach, to establish a tie.”
Minkowski sketched the conjuncture between confusion and the mechanism of the
tie. “In confusion, things that ought to come apart impinge upon each
other, they enter into each other and, in a word, get confused.” Experiences
get agglomerated, amalgamated, mixed together. No figure can then emerge with
precise contours, limits, relief, brilliance or fullness. The Gestalt therapist
recognizes there one of the clinical forms of confluence which, according to
our founders’ terminology, prevents the discovery-and-invention of a figure
in regard to a ground. As we showed in a previous study, if confluence allows
us to bind experience, then it also knows how to alienate experience by holding
it in a murky feeling from which the figure struggles to extract itself.
Another characteristic of the confluent experience can be approached through
Minkowski’s concept of “the vague.” Here again, “the
contours, limits, and boundaries prove to be compromised; partly erased, they
grow frayed, lack precision, and cease to be clear cut. But this deficiency
does not come from the various objects being substituted for each other and
getting into a muddle, the dimming or effacement points toward the object itself.”
A word is vague; needs are vague; intentionality is vague and, as long as it
remains vague, the figure will have difficulty emerging as such in the subject’s
field of experience. Yet the figure is there, nascent as it were, since it is
in formation. Confusion, or ‘the confused’, is no doubt prior since
it contaminates the emergence of the figure. From this imprecise emergence,
a form with more differentiated contours detaches itself; at first it is vague,
but it can perhaps become more precise, that is, unified. The confused is clearly
found more at the level of felt [du ressenti], or lived, experience,
whereas the vague already begins to limit, extract, to think and to come together
into a figure.
The vague and the confused make wandering, straying, and distraction possible.
The progressive differentiation to which they may give rise, with the support
of the therapist as the figure takes shape, constitutes the essential part of
the moment of pre-contact in the construction of the Gestalt. Out of the initial
confusion, the beginnings of consciousness are extracted. Combing through them
[le ratissage] allows us to gather up vague forms or experience-extracts
that, once assembled, will constitute themselves into a more and more precise
and pregnant figure.
The confused and the vague can be anxiogenic, which can lead the subject to
make hasty differentiations whose product can itself be immobilized in a fixed
form. The form gets fixed, here, because it has served its purpose containing
anxiety in a given situation, but now gets repeated, ignoring the transformations
in the originary situation.
The emergence
of a precise figure can likewise generate anxiety. Confluence allows us to interrupt
the process by a return to confusion, vagueness, or the undifferentiated.
In the construction of the Gestalt, this is a moment both particularly delicate
and potentially fertile in the therapeutic encounter, since it sets the process
of individuation back to work from the ground up. The paradigm of thinking—since
Aristotle no doubt—has reduced individuation to the individuated entity.
It is the constituted individual who structures the real, not the real that
presides over individuation. Stability [le stable], on which the notion
of the individual rests, is thus considered the very form of existence. But
in every domain, the most stable state is death. Life, on the contrary, is mobility
and process. Each moment offers the renewed possibility of taking up genesis,
of engaging becoming on the basis of the complex situations in the present,
and thus the possibility of being engaged in a recomposition of processes starting
from states.
The therapist can contribute to this process of disjoining; he can contribute
to the differentiation of composites and to the separation of linkages [conjointures].
Obviously, it is not a question of substituting new, presumably more fitting,
ties for old connections supposed to be dysfunctional. It is much more a matter
of introducing mobility in such a way that nascent experience can modulate its
available and accessible materials into creative configurations, themselves
unceasingly renewed.
It is to a truly aesthetic function that the therapist is invited in this phase
of therapeutic experience: he follows the shaping, the Gestaltung,
to the same degree that the patient sets his own aesthetic functions in motion
to constitute a figure from the elements in presence. In his own time, Freud
opposed the painter’s act to that of the sculptor. The first works by
adding matter in successive strata, and so, works by additions and layers. The
sculptor, Freud explained, proceeds by successive removals: he causes a form
to arise by removing matter, shard by shard, shaving by shaving. In the twentieth
century, artistic creation diversified the modes by which it created forms:
the painter can tear his canvas, glue and cement, scratch and cut. The sculptor
can assemble heterogeneous materials (cf. the work of Boltanski, Annette Messager,
etc.); he can work by compression or expansion (César, etc), by accumulations
and juxtapositions (Arman, etc.), wrappings and coverings (Christo); he can
solder (Giacometti), work with the Readymade (Duchamp), assemble constructions
(Panamarenko’s war or flying machines, the igloos of Mario Mertz), etc.
And why not extend the metaphor to other formal practices: making the strings
of a cello vibrate, dancing, setting the stage, orchestrating, modulating the
voice, poetizing, dramatizing, clowning, recounting, producing images, and other
metaphors. Each aesthetic practice contains its talents and its limits. Each
one teaches us new characteristics of the process of taking-shape. In the same
way, the fabrication of symptoms and dysfunction arises from this same dynamic
of taking-shape, as Rank demonstrated and as other Gestalt theorists like Michael
V. Miller have attempted to show in their approach to psychopathological phenomena.
This mode of formation or assembly allows us to approach what Merleau-Ponty
called “the speaking word” [parole parlante]. What he is
designating with this expression is the word, animated by a signifying intention
in its incipience; the word which attempts to “put into words a certain
silence” that preceded the intention itself. Merleau-Ponty opposes the
speaking word to the “spoken word” [parole parlée],
which rests upon sedimented meanings and “enjoys the available meanings
the way one enjoys an acquired fortune.” On the basis of these acquired
and available meanings, the creator, like the child, is able to produce other
expressive acts and to repeatedly transform the spoken word into word that speaks
anew. It is useful, in this regard, to read Goodman’s pages on chatter
and poetry, in Chapter VII of his Gestalt Therapy.
III
The Intention nascent, in the Body
Out of that initial chaos--vague and confused; out of that present or recovered
confluence, or again, out of that pre-differentiation which we rediscover by
working our way back behind premature differentiations, the dynamic of individuation
rests upon the formation of intentions, their identification and acknowledgement.
If we accept an hypothesis of the field [hypothèse de champ]
and thus of situated activity or the situated word, then a vague intentionality—which,
originally, is only a direction of meaning—will be more readily discovered
and/or invented on the side of the speaking word [parole parlante]
than on that of the spoken word [parole parlée]. At least we
will be searching for the speaking word within the spoken word.
The body “is not just one expressive space among all the others, but the
very origin of all the others, the very movement of expression…a primordial,
signifying operation in which what is expressed does not exist apart from the
expression itself.” Meaning animates my body as it animates my nascent
word. Intentionality and corporeity mutually awaken each other. It is not with
clear meanings or an elaborate thought that the other person communicates with
me, or I primarily with him. Rather, it is through a certain bodily style of
being, with a speaking word whether it be verbal or non-verbal. And my reception
of the other person’s intentionality is not a reflected thought. It is
not a reflective and explicit consciousness, but a certain form of my existence
in the mode of “being-affected.”
“The communication or comprehension of gestures is achieved thanks to
the reciprocity between my intentions and the gestures of the other person,
between my gestures and the intentions legible in the other’s behavior.
Everything happens as though the other’s intention inhabited my body,
or as though my intentions inhabited his. The gesture that I witness sketches
the outline of an intentional object in a kind of dotted line. This object becomes
actual, and it is fully understood when my body’s powers adjust to it
and cover it. The gesture is before me like a question, it indicates to me certain
perceptible points in the world, it invites me to join it there,” as Merleau-Ponty
writes magnificently.
It is not so much words or representations that establish primary communication,
as a signifying intention that sets words and bodies in motion within an implicit
register. There is someone facing the patient and, in an act (conscious or not),
there is an intentionality that focuses on and affects him. It is in this respect
that the tentative setting into words of the way in which the other person affects
me, reflects a certain number of indices that may allow us to shed light on
his implicit aim and thereby contribute to its differentiation.
The expressivity of the body should be distinguished from the intention to signify.
To signify, in effect, consists in using a sign to designate an object and its
meaning to another person. But expressing [exprimer] does not imply
the mediation of a sign. The smile is not a sign referring to some meaning;
the smile is the corporeal modality of meaning. It is intentionality lived by
the subject, and it will become meaning in being perceived by the other person,
and in the return he gives it.
The corporeal lived experience [vécu corporel] of a subject
is rarely independent of the intentionality it contains. In this regard, I would
invite the doubting reader to try a very simple experiment. In focusing your
consciousness subtly, gently touch, before your eyes, the tip of your left index
finger with your right index finger. Keep in mind the distinct sensations you
noted in each of your index fingers. Then do the opposite movement. That is,
touch your right index finger, this time, with your left index finger. You will
doubtless note that, at the contact point, the sensations are different according
as your finger is animated by a “touching” intentionality or by
a “being touched” intentionality. From a strictly mechanical point
of view, the sensations ought to be the same. However, when the touched reverses
into the touching, that which organizes the difference arises from a specific
intentionality, and not from some objectifiable factor.
But the sole access I can have to the other’s intentionality is tied to
his expressivity. “A priori, the other person is defined in each
system by his expressive value, that is, by his implicit and enveloping value…The
other cannot be separated from the expressivity that constitutes him…To
grasp the other as he is, we were justified in calling for specific conditions
of experience; that is, the moment in which the expressed does not yet exist
(for us) outside of that which expressed it,” as Deleuze maintains. He
even adds, “we must understand that the other person is not a structure
among others within the field of perception. He is the structure that conditions
the field in its totality, as well as the functioning of that totality.”
Phenomenology has taught us that it is impossible to separate things from their
manner of appearing to someone. This hypothesis sets us radically apart from
the belief in the neutrality of the therapist. It invites us, on the contrary,
to consider the modes according to which things appear to him as constituting
the phenomena themselves. Far from deploring the presence of my subjectivity
(including the influence it has in determining the organization of the field),
I lay claim to my “being-affected,” as a tool by which to comprehend
the other. Georges Braque said that the painter did not seek to “reconstitute
an anecdotal fact, but rather to constitute a pictorial fact.” By analogy,
I would readily say that the therapist does not seek to reconstitute an anecdotal
fact, but rather to constitute a therapeutic fact.
We are thus distancing ourselves from an approach that would call itself scientific,
in order to enter fully into an aesthetic procedure [démarche esthétique].
If I want to comprehend (and I mean to com-prehend, not to ex-plicate) and feel
light, to whom shall I turn more readily? To the physicists who speak to me
of photons and undulatory phenomena, or to the works of painters of past centuries?
The therapeutic situation is where a taking-form or taking-shape occurs; it
is a situation of construction and deconstruction of forms (Gestalts),
in and through the encounter, which may be conflictual, of two intentionalities.
Provisional Conclusion
A number of philosophical, sociological, psychological or psychotherapeutic approaches have placed the notion of the subject at the heart of their theories and practices. Our thought patterns are constructed on this prejudice. According to these approaches, the self (or the subject, etc., whatever the name we choose to give it) is assigned a forced residence because it has been confused with the individual. It is therefore shut up and alienated. The Gestalt therapy born in the 1940s and ‘50s undertook a theorization for psychotherapy that vanished into the cracks that this system of thought had begun to manifest. The cracks became breaks or gaps, and then faults, and finally a paradigm change.
Everything should be rebuilt in the perspective of the field: therapy is to be rethought as a situation; practice, as an encounter; expression, as an effect of the field. Indeed, we must rethink expression as an effect of the field before being the manifestation of a psyche--which it (the psyche) generates rather than following from that psyche.
In the therapeutic
encounter, the one and the other may be tempted to position themselves as a
priori constituted, as individuated. This is a modality that has stood
its tests over the decades. Another modality can come into being on the bases
established by our founders, and their definition of the self. As a catalyst
of functions requisite for contact with novelty and for realizing creative adjustments,
the self is engaged in the situation. The Gestalt therapist is engaged in the
situation, and this engagement is part of the very structuring of the field.
He affects the other person and the other affects him. The implicit intention
of each party can be stammeringly expressed on the basis of each one’s
experience, such as he feels and perceives it. In this respect, the moment of
pre-contact, the moment of emergence and/or construction of the figure, is determinative.
In effect, it allows us to orient ourselves in the ‘same’, that
is, in what is known, in the narrative. It may also allow us to start from an
undifferentiated site, which will have to be individuated continuously, on-goingly.
Thus, recalling Medard Boss’s tale with which we began this essay, the
therapist will have to add his “camel” to the givens of the situation,
and without even knowing what will come of it. His intentionality will simply
be to open conditions of possibility—the forms of which remain to be created.
Translated from French by Bettina BERGO
Jean-Marie Robine is a Gestalt therapist. He trains therapists and is the Director
of the Institut français de Gestalt-thérapie (Bordeaux).
He is the author of two books, La Gestalt-thérapie (Editions
Bernet-Danilo) and Gestalt-thérapie, la construction de soi
(Editions L’Harmattan). These works have been translated into several
languages.
NOTES
Medard Boss,
Introduction à la médecine psychosomatique (Paris: Presses
Universitaires de France, 1959), p. 79. [The work was translated from the 1954
edition of Boss, Grundriss der Medizin und der Psychologie]. In English,
Existential Foundations of Medicine and Psychology, Stephen Conway
and Anne Cleaves, trs. (New York: Jason Aronson, 1979).
Martin Heidegger, Zollikoner Seminäre (Frankfurt am Main: V. Klostermann,
1987), cited by Françoise Dastur, Phénoménologie et
thérapie: la question de l’autre dans les Zollikoner Seminäre
in Jean-François Courtine, ed., Figures de la subjectivité
(Paris: Editions du C.N.R.S., 1992). In English, see Franz Mayr and Richard
Askay, trs., Martin Heidegger, Zollikon Seminars: Protocols, Conversations,
Medard Boss, ed., (Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press, 2001).
Cf. M. Heidegger, Being and Time, John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson,
trs. and eds. (New York: Harper and Row, 1962), see §§ 9-11 about
the “Analytic of Dasein,” pp.67-78.
Jean-Marie Robine, “From Field to Situation,” in J.-M. Robine, ed.,
Contact and Relationship in a Field Perspective (Bordeaux: L’Exprimerie,
2001). (French translation in Cahiers de Gestalt-thérapie, No.
11, Spring 2002.
Fritz Perls, Ralph F. Hefferline, and Paul Goodman, Gestalt Therapy: Excitement
and Growth in the Human Personality (New York: Julian Press, 1951, 1969).
French translation Gestalt-thérapie, nouveauté, excitation,
et développement (Bordeaux: L’Exprimerie, 2001).
Paul Goodman, Little Prayers and the Finite Experience (New York: Harper
and Row, 1972), p. 7.
Jean-Marie Robine, “From Field to Situation,” Op. cit.
Guy Debord, Rapport sur la construction des situations (Paris: Editions
Mille et Une Nuits, 2000).
Jean-Marie Robine, “Preface” to the French translation of Perls
et al., Gestalt Therapy, Op. cit.
Gary Yontef, “Comments on ‘Boundary Processes and Boundary States’,”
Miller, in The Gestalt Journal, Vol. XI, No. 2, pp. 25-36. “Process
is often opposed to structure. However, in Gestalt therapy’s theory of
the field, we can conceive structure simply as a process that evolves slowly,
[where] states and structures lose their appearance as processes, because they
are framed in such a way that they no longer evince the dynamic aspect of the
process. The difference resides in the way in which they are framed.”
p. 29.
Franz C. Brentano, Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint, Antos C.
Rancurello, D.B. Terrell, and Linda L. McAlister, trs., (New York: Routledge,
1995).
Edmund Husserl, Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological
Philosophy (The Hague and Boston: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, 1980-1989),
Vol. I. Page 185 in the French edition.
Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology of Perception, Colin Smith, tr.,
(New York: Routledge, 2002).
Emmanuel Levinas, “Intentionality and Sensation,” (1965)
in Discovering Existence with Husserl, Richard A. Cohen and Michael
B. Smith, trs. and eds., (Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press, 1998).
John R. Searle, Intentionality: An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind (New
York: Cambridge University Press, 1983).
Jacquy Chemouni, dir., Clinique de l’intentionnalité (Paris:
In-Press Editions, 2001).
Ibid., p. 46.
Sigmund Freud, “The Ego and the Id” (1923) in James Strachey
and Anna Freud, trs. and eds., The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological
Works of Sigmund Freud, Vol. 19, (London: Hogarth Press, 1964). In French,
“Le moi et le ça,” in Sigmund Freud, Œuvres
completes (1921-1923) (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1991).
Georg Groddeck, The Book of the It, V.M.E. Collins, tr., Lawrence Durrell,
intro. (New York: Vintage Books, 1961) in French Le livre du Ça
(Paris: Gallimard, 1963).
F. S. Perls et al., Gestalt Therapy, Op. cit., 1951.
Thomas and Znaniecki, cited by M. Fornel and L. Quéré, La
logique des situations (Paris: Éditions de l’École
des Hautes Études en Sciences socials [EHESS], 1999).
Groddeck, Op. cit.
In this epigram, almost as curious in French as in English, Robine is playing
on the subject and the objective genitives. Thus, the expression can mean: “the
fact of stating what we undergo or experience,” or “the
speech, or self-expression, of the experience itself.” Leaving these two
genitives in flux is clearly the author’s intention, as it bespeaks the
experience such as he explained it in the previous paragraph.—Trans.
F. S. Perls et al., Op. cit., p. 66.
Gilles Deleuze, cited by Michael V. Miller in J.-M. Robine, Contact and
Relationship in a Field Perspective, Op. cit.
J.-M. Robine, Op. cit.
J. J. Gibson, The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception (Boston,
Mass.: Houghton Mifflin Publishers, 1979).
Hans Joas, La Créativité de l’agir (Paris: Éditions
le Cerf, 1999). In English, The Creativity of Action Jeremy Gaines
and Paul Keast, trs., (Cambridge : Polity Press, 1996).
F. S. Perls, et al., Gestalt Therapy, Op. cit., pp. 255-57.
F. S. Perls, et al., Gestalt Therapy, Op. cit., pp. 64-71.
Pietro Cavaleri, “Le concept d’intentionnalité en phénoménologie
et en Gestalt-thérapie,” translated from the Italian, in Documents
de l’Institut française de Gestalt-thérapie, No. 56,
1992. Bordeaux
Eugène Minkowski, Traité de psychopathologie (Paris:
Institut Synthélabo, Collection Les Empêcheurs de penser en rond,
1999), Chapt. III. In English, Lived time: Phenomenological and Psychopathological
Studies, Nancy Metzel, tr., (Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press,
1970).
M. Dorra, Heidegger, Primo Levi et le sequoia (Paris: Gallimard, Collection
Traces, 2001), p. 69.
E. Minkowski, Op. cit., p. 694.
Ibid., p. 696.
Ibid., p. 699.
J.-M. Robine and B. Lapeyronnie, “La confluence, expérience
liée et experience aliénée, in Robine, Gestalt-thérapie,
la construction du soi (Paris: L’Harmattan, 1997).
Minkowski, Op. cit., p. 700.
Otto Rank, L’art et l’artiste (Paris: Payot, 1984). In
English, Art and Artist : Creative Urge and Personality Development,
Charles Francis Atkinson, tr., (New York : Norton, 1989).
Michael V. Miller, La poétique de la Gestalt-thérapie (Bordeaux:
L’Exprimerie, 2001).
Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Phénoménologie de la perception
(Paris: Gallimard, 1945, 1976), p. 229. In English, Phenomenology of Perception,
Colin Smith, tr., (New York: Routledge, 2002).
Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Le visible et l’invisible, Claude Lefort,
ed., (Paris: Gallimard, 1964), p. 166. In English, The Visible and the Invisible;
Followed by Working Notes. Alphonso Lingis, tr., (Evanston Ill.: Northwestern
University Press, 1968).
Merleau-Ponty, Phénoménologie de la perception, Op. cit.,
p. 229.
F.S. Perls, et al., Gestalt Therapy, Op. cit.
In French “en corps” (bodily, corporeally) is homonymous with “encore”
(again, once again). The intention is, in fact, born afresh in the Gestaltung
described in Section II. The focus, now, is on the relation between intentionality
and the body—Trans.
Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology of Perception, (French, 171, 193).
Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology of Perception, Op. cit., pp.
(French, pp. 215-216).
Gilles Deleuze, Différence et Répétition (Paris:
Presses Universitaires de France, 1968), pp. 334-35; in English, Difference
and Repetition, Paul Patton, tr. (New York: Columbia University Press,
1994).
Gilles Deleuze, Logique du sens (Paris: Éditions de Minuit,
1969), p. 58. In English, The Logic of Sense, Mark Lester with Charles
Stivale, trs., Constantin V. Boundas, ed., (New York: Columbia University Press,
1990).
Georges Braque, Cahier (1917-1955) (Paris: Fondation Maeght, 1994),
p. 30. In English, Illustrated notebooks, 1917-1955, Stanley Appelbaum,
tr., (New York, Dover Publications, 1971).
Jean-Marie Robine
E-mail: jmr-gestalt@orange.fr
Recebido em:
11/08/2009.
Aprovado em: 08/10/2009.